SciELO - Scientific Electronic Library Online

 
vol.2 issue3Miguel de Unamuno, tragedia y esperanza. ¿Qué debemos hacer y qué podemos esperar?Metafísica y dinámica caótica author indexsubject indexsearch form
Home Pagealphabetic serial listing  

Services on Demand

Journal

Article

Indicators

Related links

  • Have no similar articlesSimilars in SciELO

Share


Valenciana

Print version ISSN 2007-2538

Valenciana vol.2 n.3 Valenciana Jan./Jun. 2009

https://doi.org/10.15174/rv.v0i3.256 

Artículos

Autoconciencia prerreflexiva: dos argumentos contra las teorías representacionales de la conciencia

Israel Grande-García1 

1Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas, UNAM.


Resumen

Las teorías representacionales de la conciencia intentan dar cuenta de la experiencia fenoménica con términos mentales sin implicar la conciencia. Las dos principales son el representacionalismo y las teorías de representación de orden superior. El principal argumento para la primera es el de la transparencia de la experiencia, según el cual es imposible discernir, vía introspección, las propiedades intrínsecas de una experiencia de x que no se experimenten como propiedades de x. El representacionalismo sostiene que nuestras experiencias muestran rasgos cualitativos que son idénticos a las propiedades de los objetos que nuestra experiencia representa y que, por lo tanto, el carácter fenoménico de la experiencia es idéntico a su contenido representacional. Las teorías de representación de orden superior o HOR (por higher-order representation), por su parte, explican los estados conscientes en términos de una representación de orden superior, que puede tomar la forma de una cuasi percepción o un pensamiento que va dirigido a un estado mental de primer orden. En este artículo presento dos argumentos contra las teorías representacionales desde una teoría que establece que toda experiencia consciente lleva implícita un tipo de autoconciencia prerreflexiva caracterizada por tener un aspecto por tener un aspecto: ser característicamente mía o para mí (sentido de pertenencia). El primer argumento es contra el representacionalismo. El argumento sostiene que este sentido de pertenencia (1) es un rasgo intrínseco de la experiencia y (2) es discernible por medio de la introspección; por lo tanto, el carácter fenoménico de la experiencia no es idéntico a su contenido representacional y por consiguiente, el representacionalismo es erróneo. El segundo argumento es el problema de los estados de orden superior sin un objetivo al cual dirigirse (i.e., un estado mental de primer orden). Supongamos que un sujeto S tiene una representación de orden superior (HOR) de encontrarse en un estado de dolor d, pero sin tener d. Según las teorías HOR, d no es consciente porque no existe. Pero, como S tiene una HOR acerca de d entonces tendrá una experiencia fenoménica de d. No obstante este resultado es incoherente. Para la teoría de la autoconciencia prerreflexiva, d no es consciente si no le pertenece a S, pero como S tiene conciencia de d (siendo d otro tipo de estado diferente al dolor, e.g., una creencia, una imaginería mental), entonces este sentido de pertenencia es lo que hace que d sea una experiencia fenoménica.

Palabras clave: conciencia fenoménica; autoconciencia prerreflexiva; sentido de pertenencia; representacionalismo; representación de orden superior

Abstract

Representational theories of consciousness try to explain phenomenal experience by the use of terms without implying consciousness. The two main theories are representationalism and higher-order representational theories (HOR). The key argument for the first one is the transparency of experience according to which, it is impossible to discern, via introspection, any intrinsic properties of an experience of x that are not experienced as properties of x. Representationalism states that our experiences show qualitative features that are identical to the properties things are represented as having, and therefore, phenomenal character of experience is identical to its representational content. On the other hand, HOR theories account for conscious states in terms of higher-order representation, that may take the form of a quasi-perception or a thought that it’s directed to a first-order mental state. In this paper I put forward two arguments against representational theories, on the basis of a theory which affirms that every conscious experience has an implicit pre-reflective self-consciousness of some kind, that it is characterized of having a for-me-ness aspect (sense of ownership). The first argument is against representationalism. The argument asserts that this sense of ownership (1) is an intrinsic aspect of experience, and (2) is discernible via introspection; therefore, the phenomenal character of experiences is not identical to its representational content, and consequently, representationalism is false. The second argument is the problema being in a pain state p, but without having p. According to HOR theories, p is non-conscious, because it doesn’t exist. But, S’s having HOR about p, will cause that S would have a phenomenal experience of p. Nevertheless this result in incoherent. For pre-reflexive self-consciousness theory, on the other hand, p will not be a conscious state if it doesn’t belong to S, nevertheless S does have consciousness of p (being p different from pain, e.g., a believe, a mental imagery) therefore this sense of ownership is what makes p a phenomenal experience.

Keywords: phenomenal consciousness; pre-reflective self-consciousness; sense of ownership; representationalism; higher-order representation

Texto completo disponible sólo en PDF.

Bibliografía

Aquila, Richard, 1990, “Consciousness and higher-order thoughts: Two objections”, en American Philosophical Quarterly, núm. 27, pp. 81-87. [ Links ]

Armstrong, David Malet, 1981, The Nature of Mind, The Harvester Press, Sussex. [ Links ]

Baars, Bernard, Thomas Z. Ramsoy y Steven Laureys, 2003, “Brain, conscious experience and the observing self ”, en Trends in Neurosciences, núm 26, pp. 671-675. [ Links ]

Bermúdez, José Luis, Anthony Marcel y Naomi Eilan (eds.), 1995, The Body and the Self, MIT, Cambridge. [ Links ]

Byrne, Alex, 1997, “Some like it HOT: Consciousness and higher-order thoughts”, en Philosophical Studies, núm. 86, pp. 103-129. [ Links ]

Carruthers, Peter, 2000, Phenomenal Consciousness: A Naturalistic Theory, Cambridge University Press, Nueva York. [ Links ]

Caston, Victor, 2002, “Aristotle on consciousness”, en Mind, núm. 111, pp. 751-815. [ Links ]

Chalmers, David John, 2004, “The representational character of experience”, en Brian Leiter (ed.), The Future for Philosophy, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 153-181. [ Links ]

Churchland, Paul M., 1988, Matter and Consciousness: A Contemporary Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind, MIT, Cambridge. [ Links ]

Crane, Tim, 2003, “The intentional structure of consciousness”, en Smith, Quentin y Aleksandar Jokic (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 33-56. [ Links ]

Dretske, Fred, 1995, Naturalizing the Mind, MIT, Cambridge. [ Links ]

_____, “Experience as representation”, en Philosophical Issues, núm. 13, pp. 67-82. [ Links ]

Drummond, John, 2006, “The case(s) of (self-)awareness”, en Kriegel, Uriah y Keneth Williford (eds.), Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness, MIT, Cambridge, pp. 199-220. [ Links ]

Gallagher, Shaun, 2005, How the Body Shapes the Mind, Oxford University Press, Oxford. [ Links ]

_______, 2007, “The natural philosophy of agency”, en Philosophy Compass, núm. 2, pp. 1-11. [ Links ]

_______ y Dan Zahavi, 2008, The Phenomenological Mind: An Introduction to Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science, Routledge, Londres. [ Links ]

Gennaro, Rocco J., 1996, Consciousness and Self-Consciousness: A Defense of the Higher-Order Thought Theory of Consciousness, John Benjamins, Philadelphia. [ Links ]

Gray, Jeffrey, 2004, Consciousness: Creeping Up On the Hard Problem, Oxford University Press, Oxford. [ Links ]

Haikonen, Pentti O., 2007, Robot Brains: Circuits and Systems for Conscious Machines, John Wiley & Sons, West Sussex. [ Links ]

Harman, Gilbert, 1990, “The intrinsic quality of experience”, en James E. Tomberlin (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, 4: Action Theory and Philosophy of Mind, Ridgeview Publishing, Atascadero, pp. 31-52. [ Links ]

Janzen, Greg, 2006a, “Phenomenal character as implicit self-awareness”, en Journal of Consciousness Studies, núm. 13, pp. 44-73. [ Links ]

_______, 2006b, “The representational theory of phenomenal character: a phenomenological critique”, en Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, núm. 5, pp. 321-339. [ Links ]

Kind, Amy, 2003, “What’s so transparent about transparency?”, enPhilosophical Studies, núm. 115, pp. 225-344. [ Links ]

_______, 2007, “Restrictions on representationalism”, en Philosophical Studies, núm. 134, pp. 405-427. [ Links ]

Kriegel, Uriah, 2007, “Philosophical theories of consciousness: contemporary western perspectives”, en Zelazo, Philip David, Morris Moscovitch y Evan Thompson (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness, Cambridge University Press, Nueva York, pp. 35-66. [ Links ]

_______ y Keneth Williford (eds.), 2006, Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness, MIT, Cambridge. [ Links ]

Legrand, Dorothée, 2005, “Le soi corporel”, en L’Évolution Psychiatrique, núm. 70, pp. 709-719. [ Links ]

_______, 2006, “The bodily self: The sensori-motor roots of pre-reflective selfconsciousness”, en Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, núm. 5, pp. 89-118. [ Links ]

_______, 2007, “Pre-reflective self-as-subject from experiential and empirical perspectives”, en Consciousness and Cognition, núm. 16, pp. 583-599. [ Links ]

Levine, Joseph, 2001, Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness, Oxford University Press, Oxford. [ Links ]

Lycan, William G., 1995, “A limited defence of phenomenal information”, en Thomas Metzinger (ed.), Conscious Experience, Imprint Academic, Reino Unido, pp. 243-258. [ Links ]

_______, 1996, Consciousness and Experience, MIT, Cambridge. [ Links ]

Martin, M.G.F., 1995, “Bodily awareness: A sense of ownership”, en José Luis Bermúdez, Anthony Marcel y Naomi Eilan (eds.), The Body and the Self, MIT, Cambridge, pp. 267-289. [ Links ]

Nagel, Thomas, 1974, “What is it like to be a bat?”, en The Philosophical Review, núm. 83, pp. 435-450. [ Links ]

Neander, Karen, 1998, “The division of phenomenal labor: A problem for representational theories of consciousness”, en Philosophical Perspectives, núm. 12, pp. 411-434. [ Links ]

Newen, Albert y Kai Vogeley 2003, “Self-representation: Searching for a neural signature of self-consciousness”, en Consciousness and Cognition, núm. 12, pp. 529-543. [ Links ]

Pitt, David, “Mental representation”, en Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, en línea: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mentalrepresentation. [ Links ]

Roessler, Johannes y Naomi Eilan (eds.), 2003, Agency and Self-Awareness: Issues in Philosophy and Psychology, Oxford University Press, Oxford. [ Links ]

Rosenthal, David M., 1993, “Higher-order thoughts and the appendage theory of consciousnes”, en Philosophical Psychology, núm. 6, pp. 155-166. [ Links ]

_______, 1997, “A theory of consciousness”, en Ned Block, Owen Flanagan y Güven Güzeldere (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, MIT, Cambridge, pp. 729-753. [ Links ]

_______, 2002, “Explaining consciousness”, en David J. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings, Oxford University Press, Nueva York, pp. 406-421. [ Links ]

Rowlands, Mark, 2001, The Nature of Consciousness, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2001. [ Links ]

Seager, William, 1999, Theories of Consciousness: An Introduction and Assessment, Routledge, Londres. [ Links ]

Seeley, William W. y Virginia E. Sturm, 2007, “Self-representation and the frontal lobes”, en Bruce L. Miller y Jeffrey L. Cummings (eds.), The Human Frontal Lobes: Functions and Disorders, The Guilford Press, Nueva York, pp. 317-334. [ Links ]

Synofzik, Matthis, Gottfried Vosgerau y Albert Newen, 2008, “I move, therefore I am: a new theoretical framework to investigate agency and ownership”, en Consciousness and Cognition, núm.17, pp. 411-424. [ Links ]

Textor, Mark, 2006, “Brentano (and some neo-Brentanians) on inner consciousness”, en Dialectica, núm. 60, pp. 411-432. [ Links ]

Thompson, Evan, 2007, Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind, The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge. [ Links ]

_______ y Dan Zahavi, 2007, “Philosophical issues: phenomenology”, en Philip David Zelazo, Morris Moscovitch y Evan Thompson (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness, Cambridge University Press, Nueva York, pp. 67-87. [ Links ]

Tye, Michael, 1995, Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind, MIT, Cambridge. [ Links ]

_______, 2000, Consciousness, Color, and Content, MIT, Cambridge. [ Links ]

_______, 2009, Consciousness Revisited: Materialism without Phenomenal Concepts, MIT, Cambridge. [ Links ]

Wider, Kathleen V., 1997, The Bodily Nature of Consciousness: Sartre and Contemporary Philosophy of Mind, Cornell University Press, Ithaca. [ Links ]

Zahavi, Dan, 2004, “Back to Brentano?”, en Journal of Consciousness Studies, núm 11, pp. 66-87. [ Links ]

_______, 2005, Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating the First-Person Perspective, MIT, Cambridge. [ Links ]

Creative Commons License Este es un artículo publicado en acceso abierto bajo una licencia Creative Commons