SciELO - Scientific Electronic Library Online

 
vol.29Poder simbólico, illusio y afectividad en la sociología de Pierre BourdieuPolíticas de igualdad de género e interseccionalidad: estrategias y claves de articulación índice de autoresíndice de assuntospesquisa de artigos
Home Pagelista alfabética de periódicos  

Serviços Personalizados

Journal

Artigo

Indicadores

Links relacionados

  • Não possue artigos similaresSimilares em SciELO

Compartilhar


Convergencia

versão On-line ISSN 2448-5799versão impressa ISSN 1405-1435

Convergencia vol.29  Toluca  2022  Epub 22-Ago-2022

https://doi.org/10.29101/crcs.v29i0.17440 

Scientific Articles

Elements for an Immanent Critique of the Political Economy of Modern Space

1Pontificia Universidad Católica de Valparaíso, Chile, robertovmu@gmail.com

2Universidad Alberto Hurtado, Chile, igasic@uahurtado.cl

3Universidad Católica Silva Henríquez, Chile, angelo.narvaez.l@gmail.com


Abstract:

Our purpose is to present a logical sequence that accounts for the way in which the critique of political economy (Marx) is categorically articulated and configured with the production of space (Lefebvre). Methodologically, we carry out a comparative categorical approach to the concepts of criticism, immanence, production, modern space-time, and the urban from various epistemological trajectories as primary and secondary sources. Our results indicate that an immanent critique of the political economy of space makes it possible to delimit the critique of capital and the production of modern space-time as a social totality. We conclude that the critique of modernity from the critique of the political economy of space is a critique of the abstract logic of value and its expression in the social production of abstract space-time, where urban space is the geographic space produced for the reproduction of capital and the place of exchange where the totality of mercantile production takes place.

Key words: critique of political economy of space; immanent critique; modern space-time; urbanization.

Resumen:

Nuestro objetivo es presentar una secuencia lógica que dé cuenta del modo en que la crítica de la economía política (Marx) se articula y configura categorialmente con la producción del espacio (Lefebvre). Metodológicamente, realizamos una aproximación categorial comparativa de los conceptos de crítica, inmanencia, producción, espacio-tiempo moderno y lo urbano desde varias trayectorias epistemológicas en tanto fuentes primarias y secundarias. Nuestros resultados indican que una crítica inmanente de la economía política del espacio permite delimitar la crítica del capital y la producción del espacio-tiempo moderno como una totalidad social. Concluimos que la crítica de la modernidad desde la crítica de la economía política del espacio es una crítica de la lógica abstracta del valor y su expresión en la producción social del espacio-tiempo abstracto, donde el espacio urbano es el espacio geográfico producido para la reproducción del capital y el lugar de intercambio donde se realiza la totalidad de la producción mercantil.

Palabras clave: crítica de la economía política del espacio; crítica inmanente; espacio-tiempo moderno; urbanización.

Introduction

In the present article we intend to put forward some minimal aspects of the general project of a critique to the political economy of space as an unavoidable dimension of the abstract domination of modernity. We develop a critique of the political economy of urban space from rereading Lefebvre, with a view to contributing to the conceptualization of the urban as regards the specifically capitalist mode of production of space. These theses do not have a univocal or normative, instead they point at systematizing some of the debates in a logical, not necessarily historic. We intend to expose a logical sequence that gives an account of the way in which the critique of the political economy of space has been configured more sinuously that linearly.

The international experience in 1968, the 1973 oil crisis, the Latin American dictatorships, the failure of the Yugoslavian model, the fall of the USSR, the reconfiguration of the Gulf and the quick rise of the Chinese economic model after the 1979 reforms, implicated that economy and social sciences were faced with the need to represent the global space under new parameters and think of the same concept of space from new epistemological trajectories that have been obviated along the century. Lefebvre’s studies on urban societies (2018 a , 2018b, 2018c, 2015) and the change of David Harvey to Marxism (2007) are likely the best know examples and most worked in the critical analyses with the goal of examining the spatial of the United States’ hegemony after WWII, strongly marked by the mass consumption, mass culture and digital communication media

In parallel, the rediscovery of Gramsci in Latin America hinted the appearance of dependentist and decolonial theories as of the mid 1970’s, and from there, indirectly in economic structuralism, subordinate studies and the postcolonial critique adopted by the spatial theses on center, periphery and semi—periphery put forward by CEPAL (Bielschowsky, 2010) . Paradoxically, CEPAL, which had important influence on Latina American developmentalist projects, particularly in Brazil and the Southern Cone, found a rather strong opposition in a sizeable part of the world of the capital they themselves have contributed to conceptualize and channel from new productive and distributive formulas. The general logic of value seemed not to give a rest in the global process of neoliberalization and translated into the urgency of returning to a critique to the political economy that some disavowed too soon, focusing on the particularisms, language autonomy, discourse, communicative action, et cetera, and that others considered and object of orthodox archaeology.

In this historic context, one of the main tasks of the critical theory in its broadest range was precisely redefining the meaning of the critique. In his opening allocution of the Frankfurt School: “The current situation of social philosophy and the tasks of an institute for social research”, Max Horkheimer stated that the main task of the criticism was to interpret again, to turn to the analysis of reality as it was being configured. The ideal of Horkheimer, Adorno, Pollock, etc., entailed a re—elaboration of the general critique, and of the political economy critique in particular (Horkheimer, 1996: 398).

In spite of its difficulties and ambiguities, re—elaborating an interpretation of the theory of value to enable the formulation of new questions was part of the gesture that Lefebvre and Harvey retook the critical tradition of heterodox Marxism, despite their respective confidence in several political dimensions of the traditional occidental Marxism. The critique to the political economy, according to Lefebvre and Harvey, was at least incomplete if it did not consider a transversal aspect to every realization process of the logic of value, namely: the general production of a social space able to subsume in formal and actual terms each of the moments that are differentiated in modernity: economy, politics, culture, but also production, interchange, consumption, distribution, and accumulation of capital, at local and global level.

In this respect, Lefebvre stated in The Production of Space, the critique to political economy would be hardly able to continue if the history of capital was not presented in parallel to that of space because in their literal mutual coincidence “the proper historical period of the history of space concurs with capital accumulation, beginning with its primitive phase” and “concluding with the global market under the reign of abstraction” and its specific form of domination (Lefebvre, 2013: 181). When we try to return to the critique of political economy, Lefebvre expressed that one of the main problems of is the concept of production, traditionally associated with the logic of labor/surplus through occidental Marxism. However, while “the more the meaning [of production] is increasingly intended to be consolidated”, “the less the creative capacity that connotes invention, imagination; instead, only work is usually referred” (Lefebvre, 2013: 126). Quite the contrary, it seemed necessary to speak of “production of knowledge, ideology and meanings, images, discourses, language, symbols and signs” because there is “an abusive use of the procedure that Marsx and Engels utilized in a naïve manner: provide the extensive meaning [of production], that is philosophical, with a narrow meaning, scientific (economic)” (Lefebvre, 2013), which inversely is also valid for the intension of reducing the critique to the capitalist space and to the abstract domination to language, subjectivity, et cetera.

The strict projection of the theory of value reduced the long logical—historic process of the enhanced reproduction of capita to certain moments preferable in the analysis. In this way, for example, focusing on accumulation became the overestimation of the relationship labor/surplus value, while paying attention to redistribution turned into various forms of fiscal and tax contention (from Tobin rate to the identification of Pikletti’s hypotheses as the informal economic propositions of political institutionalism and the redistributive propositions of the so—called twenty—first century Socialism). Quite the contrary, the margins of the Marxian critique to political economy are not restricted to Capital, or some of its chapters, but are already configured in the Grundrisse in1857—58 up to the re—elaborations of the exposition of the theory of value after 1867.

Currently, the contemporary rereading of Marxists tradition, from a categorial and logical dimension —frequently antagonistic to each other— that revitalized the new interpretations of Marx’s late theory of value (Kurz, 2016; Postone, 1993; Reichelt, 2001; Bellofiore, 2018 a ; Backhaus, 1997; Heinrich, 2018) , and also from the economic and social dimension that retrieved and updated the thesis of social space, nature, imperialism and uneven and combined development of capitalism (Bellamy Foster, 2008; Moore, 2020). Even liberal economists such as Stiglitz, Krugman, Akerlof, and Shiller contested the hegemonic analytic paradigms of the XX century, at once, of course, they celebrated the death of Marx once more (Stiglitz, 2006; Krugman, 1999; Akerlof and Shiller, 2016).

From plane to language, from language to space

The idea of modern production has several possible trajectories which, apparently, almost every one reaches the Cartesian notion of absolute plane. The Cartesian deduction of space as the experience plane of res extensa is still today the basis of empirical sciences: things take place in a referred place on a plane full of universally analogue coordinates. Some years later, Pascal reached an utterly different conclusion following Torricelli’s experiments: although absolute, space is a unit devoid of all the possible. In the long disciplinary trajectory of modern sciences between XVI and XIX centuries, the notion of full space was imposed with especial force on the various empirical sciences, from biology to geography, and even sociology.

When Kant developed his theory of space and time as inseparable conditions for the possibility of experience and representation, without themselves being representations, that is to say, pure concepts of intuition, he took time—space from the objectivity plane to that of subjectivity. Kant’s epistemological11Copernican revolution, was in placing the subject as the condition of possibility of the configuration of images and concrete representations, including natural landscapes —what we see, Kant said, is a forest, not x number of trees—. Hegel carried on with the Kantian argument stating that essences —of the things, of the space— exists, but only on condition that they are essential due to their essentiality; that is to say, because of the transient and variable nature of what they constitute. At least one of Hegel’s examples does not make much room for ambiguity: the essence of state power of the reign of Louis XIV is effectively substantiated in God; however, after the Revolution and the Déclaration of 1789, power resides in man —not any man, but on the male white proprietor, of course, not in God anymore—. What does it mean? With Hegel, Kantian subjectivity leaves the plane of transcendence to enter into the plane o immanence.

What is the relation between this and social space? Hegel understands space as an immanent configuration, that is to say, there is no essence in the background of the phenomenon (the noumenon of Kantian phenomenon), but only essential phenomena: this is what Hegel calls experience, where “behind the curtain call… there is nothing to see, unless we go behind it ourselves, both in order to see, and also there is something to see behind the curtain” (Hegel, 2010: 104). In this sense, there are essences as socially produced essences, owing to this Merleau—Ponty (1996: 165) states “from Hegel, militant philosophy reflects no longer on subjectivity, but on intersubjectivity”

Lefebvre retook the idea by saying that “modernity is Hegelian” because there “the linking between power and knowledge” is affirmed under the form of State, but “the modern world is Marxists” as well, Lefevre said: first, because such State that subsumes society also codifies the continuation of capital, and because the Marxian principle is not that of need, but that of possibility. If room is made for the possibility, Lefebvre concludes, the modern world is ultimately Nietzschean as well, because “despite the efforts of political forces to affirm themselves above the lived, to subordinate society”, the modern world carries the mark of “the obstinate defense of civilization against state, social and moral pressures” (Lefebvre, 1980: 3). In this sense, it is not only or first and foremost the space as such, but in the way the trajectory of modernity produces a spatial logic from which empirical formulas come out, as a park, a prison, a psychiatric hospital or flows for modern capital. In this contextual context of modern philosophy faced by Lefebvre, from Descartes to Hegel, one of the first forms acquired by the critique to space is the criticism to its intersubjective (social) nature: if the absolute space of modernity is intersubjective, its critique has to be intersubjective as well, i.e., immanent.

When Lefebvre wonders about the determinations of modernity and befalls on the Hegelian, Marxists and Nietzschean problem, he also wonders: “and why not Heidegger?”. The answer is because it “darkens the most concrete history in Hegel and Marx, without reaching the Nietzschean critical force. Heidegger’s philosophy, a “a dissimulated theodicy, barely secularized”, faces the history of philosophy and the history of space “without looking through a radical criticism” (Lefebvre, 1980: 59). Even if Heidegger was one of the first in noticing the tendency toward the instrumental rationalization of modernity, and thereby, toward the technification of the representation of nature, for “him, a Being has language and constructions as a place of abidance”, from which he extracts a “disquieting apology of German language […] which hinders a criticism if the occidental (European) logos(Lefebvre, 1980: 60). What does this mean? In Heidegger, the critique of modernity transforms into an intension to return to premodernity where the world of Being had not been subsumed by the world of entities; that is to say, things. After a first radical opposition to the theses of Being and time in 1927, a re—appropriation takes place after WWII, especially after the encounter with Art and Space in 1969.12

The background of this problem is that in modernity, the abstract form of capital generates the norm of order and configuration: that is to say, of social domination. This is the radical aspect of Lefebvre’s conceptualization, namely: the subordination of the world of the entities is produced by the capital in an abstract manner, thereby, transgression and the eventual subversion of that abstract domination is only actually concrete when the logics of the capitalist abstraction of modernity transform (are realized). That is to say, an immanent critique to the space of capital is also a criticism to modernity.

The criticism in the critique to political economy and the place of production

If the project of late Marx of the critique to political economy that began with Grundrisse is considered it is possible to substantiate a critique to modernity and in particular, one to the political economy of space with a specific meaning: the critique to the capital. Marx stated that capital is an economic power which dominates everything in bourgeoise society [Das Kapital ist die alles beherrschende ökonomische Macht der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft] (Marx, 1945: 26); therefore, it is a starting and arrival point, it is premise of the modern socialization process, it is a basic concept of the economy and modern society [der Grundbegriff der modernen Ökonomie (...) die Grundlage der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft] (Marx, 1945: 237). Though, what is this project of critique to political economy about? Indubitably, it is a categorial critique to the economic and liberal thinking that goes from XVIII to XIX centuries, with particular emphasis on the work of Adam Smith and David Ricardo, whom Marx recognizes as founders of classic economy; however, as a categorial critique, it is also an epistemological criticism, as it deals with the conditions of possibility or the constitutive presuppositions of the basic categories of the mode of production and the mode under which they have to be critically presented [...ist Kritik der ökonomischen Kategorien oder, if you Iike, das System der bürgerlichen Ökonomie kritisch dargestellt. Es ist zugleich Darstellung des Systems und durch die Darstellung Kritik desselben] (Marx, 1978: 550).

Well now, the criticism [Kritik] in the critique to political economy is not expressed as an alternative to the mode of exposition and the content of the classic categories because it is also a critique to the capitalist socialization process [Vergesellschaftung]. Marx builds a critical system of economic categories to understand the modern commodity—producing system and inaugurates a critical presentation mode of the internal structure of capitalism, a critical exposure of the categories that configure the capitalist social formation. Only in this way is it possible to speak of a method in Marx, far from the reading of classic Marxism (which tried to apply a dialectical method as an abstract logical system to specific and determined historical phenomena), as well as the contemporary readings of the traditional method of social sciences exclusively based on the validation context.

From this standpoint, the denomination of the theoretical production of late Marx as historicism is inaccurate, not to say equivocal, or at least is not historicist in the sense of the previous paragraphs. Marx does not try to found an ontology of history from the historical development of capitalism in the cities of Manchester of London in the XIX century, or the competence capitalism that would take place —or would reach its expositive validation—exclusively in imperialism (Heinrich, 2018) ; instead, what it does is to present in a critical manner the general logic of capital and its simplest categories, that is to say, the internal organization of the capitalist mode of production in its ideal term [die innere Organisation der kapitalistischen Produktionsweise, sozusagen in ihrem idealen Durchschnit, darzustellen haben] (Marx, 2012: 839), though not in an evolutionary sense, since these are the social objective forms of the capitalist formation (Postone, 1993).

The Marxian scope of the critique is an epistemological exercise, which in addition to unfolding as a critique of other categorial registers, works as the construction of a new theoretical field to rethink the capitalist economy and the space—time conditoni of modernity. In this sense, it is something more, as it will be exposed in the following sections.

As stated by Bellofiore, the critique to political economy needs a theoretical mediation which in this case is in the classic economy exposed in the David Ricardo’s On the principles of political economy and taxation. Neither Smith nor Ricardo —trying to solve the ambiguities of The wealth of nations— managed to explain surplus or value as a social relation derived from labor, much less from capital. Political economy was unable to explain how it produces capital and how such capital is produced because it was incapable of explaining the valued presented in the form of money and also, distinguishing between labor force and live labor, or between concrete and abstract labor (Bellofiore, 2018a and 2018b).

A fundamental category of the critique to political economy is production (Produktion), whose use Marx presents briefly though systematically in the two first sections of the famous 1857 Introduction or Notebook M(Marx, 1945:121). In political economy (production, distribution, interchange and consumption) lack a meaning of totality, and frequently in the history of economic thinking it is possible to observe a tendency to absolutization each of them, and even their naturalization. Even if the project of the classic political economy stressed production, it did not manage to explain the nature a cause of the (abstract) modern wealth as a derivation from (abstract) labor. After long time, because of J. S. Mill, wrongly, the classic project ended up as an additive theory of production costs (salary, profit and income), leaving in an impasse the theory of value started by Adam Smith. Marginality, for its part, by dissipating the production process and crystalize in the theater of interchange exclusively the determination of value, nullified the conditions of possibility to think of the totality of the social process, fragmenting the field of interchange as regards the other economic activities. On the contrary, Marx developed a presentation or critical exposition [die kritische Darstellung] of the bourgeoise society’s concrete determinations [bürgerliche Gesellschaft] (Marx, 2012: 827), whose conceptualization supposes that reality may be represented as a totality, in this case, the logic from which the capitalist production mode works. However, prior to the presentation of the categories —and its mystifying nature— which Marx exposes in Capital, it may be said that the concept of “production in general” predates the set of the argumentation as an epistemic supposition.13

In Introduction, the production concept (Produktion) declines in at least four levels: as production in general, production of a given social state, as a form of specific production, and as totality of production (Dussel, 1984 and 1985). Marxian analytical and methodical effort of Capital begins with the critical presentation of commodities, a basic and privileged category to define capitalism; it does not start from the totality of bourgeoise society (objective of the first part of Introduction), but assumes the existence of capitalism from the presentation of categories, as in modern bourgeoise society commodities are the basic for of wealth. Hence, to reach the concept of production as a prelude to commodity at a concrete level, production must be related to distribution, interchange and consumption, that is to say, co—determined. As co—determinations, these articulate the totality, and in their differentiation and no—identity, they are the determining constitutive moments of totality. Here, production is socially determined, i.e., it has received the mark of a society (Dussel, 1984).

When Adorno exposed the category of socialization (Vergesellschaftung) in the 1968 Course, he stated that its essence is determination by interchange. The abstraction of exchange value turns into the domination of society over it members, of the general on the particular, it is the reduction of human subjectivity to personifications of value or condition of the interchange of commodities. All fall —Adorno states— to the law of independent interchange of their conscience as it is the social basic link of modernity (Adorno, 1975). With the generalization of interchange, the commodity form of goods becomes the generalized form of interchange, which as we have observed, can only be understood in a co—determined relation with production. Partially, that is the reason why in the Marxian analytical exercise of the first tome of Capital, the presentation begins with commodity, not production itself; that is to say, Marx privileges an abstract approach to commodity already supposing capitalist production.

In the modern social formation, commodities acquire a use value and exchange value as a property socially defined in capitalism, product of the socialization process. Conversely, value as objectification of equivalent human labor —whose for of expression is exchange value— has a social fundament on the labor that produces commodities and as an expression of a social relationship, it is a specter that finds social reality in the body of commodities, which as commodity—money carries value, whose property is expressed in the metamorphosis of commodity (C—M—C); that is to say, money as money and general logic of capital (M—C—M’); that is to say, money as capital. Value manages to valorize and therefore, to increase only in the general logic of capitalism, becoming the surplus value from subsuming abstract labor, the substance of capital.

Capital acquires special social power in modernity. Capitalists personify capital, that is to say, by means of their actions they update the movement of the value subsumed in the logic of capital, hence, it is not the capitalist who conducts the process, but the capitalist logic (the capital) [das Kapital —und der Kapitalist ist nur das personifizierte Kapital, fungiert im Produktionsprozeß nur als Träger des Kapitals—], whose social power turns things in things of value, in commodities. The social power of this logic does not depend on any law derived from individual, State or market action, neither any social class; nor capitalists nor workers. It is a social law that works hiding from society, is blind and independent from the conscience of the production agents. In its immanence, this law is organized from capital and its social characteristic consists in becoming the abstract universality of modernity —as commodities and abstract labor are generalized as the simple and basic forms of social mediation.

The development of this functioning logic becomes a false ontologization of the concepts of economy, politics as well as those of public space and private space (Kurz, 1994) . According to Robert Kurz, premodern societies do not have such differences spheres, but such differentiation is proper to modern consciousness that de—historicizes the forms of socialization, imposing them as natural conditions of mediation. Kurz (1994), who makes a parallelism between premodern and modern abstract universality, states that in the former that universality is determined by a fetishist system, which in modern language we call religion, at once, such fetishist system comprises all the reproduction of life that contains what we modernly distinguish as economy and politics. In premodern abstract universality, religion is not an “ideologic superstructure”, but as the basic form of mediation and reproduction of social life. In this regard, Kurz is not far from the Hegelian exercise: the premodern societies’ raison d’être is not more or less volatile than the logic of modern society, but in its transformation as the curtain opens it changes the entire staging now conducted by the capital. Modernity’s abstract universality does not appear as a totality, instead, it is already mediated by differenced spheres and apparently autonomous between each other, where both correspond to the form of totality of the modern fetishist constitution that appears as a functional sphere we call “economy”. From this we conclude that it is not possible to deduce that economy, city, the State or market, classes, et cetera, “produce space”, such action can only correspond to a mediated activity of capital regarding itself such as abstract universality of modernity.

The annihilation of space by time, or the space—time relation of the logic of capital

The critique to political economy is a critique to modernity, that is to say, of the formal and actual subsuming of socialized humanity by the abstract form of the valorization of value. In this sense, the immanent critique [Immanente Kritk] of Marx not only points at the new science in the making and its epochal consciousness when he criticizes the capitalist mode of production, but also criticizes the bourgeois social relationships of modern life. Being so, should not this formalization imply logically and immanently time and space?

The contemporary exercise of re—reading Marx with the prism of the critique to political economy and specially from the theory of value has been marked more by a concern about the pattern of temporality under the abstract form of value in the era of capital, than an analytical exercise of space—time mediations of capital and their expression in daily life under the rule of capital. Such is the case of Postone (1993) , who stated that the centrality of Marxian analysis is in the problem of the tyranny of time in the modern bourgeoise society.14

Against the readings on the undervaluation of space regarding time, Fischbach states that space—time and capital is much more evident than the relationship capital and time, and that Marx had already given an early account of this with the clarifications in Manifesto on the expansion and global unification of capital, as well as its tendency to break the empirical differences and geographic barriers.15 And indeed, in Manifesto, the behavior of capital is described as essentially spatial, referring the geographic space as absolute space. However, it is the late Marx of Grundrisse, who conceptualized such spatial dynamic under a more robust theory regarding the determination of value and the space—time transformations of capitalism, where despite he did not categorized space, he did use logically and immanently the concepts in its absolute and relative meanings (Harvey, 2012 a ; 2018).

With the tendency to the universalization of interchange, capital in modernity is generally prone to spatialize things making them commodities, as with the arrival of modern society, value transforms into the concrete essence the real, carrying an unavoidable and immanent space—time determination (Fischbach, 2012: 86) . This conclusion made Marx carefully produce a theoretical critique of capitalism categorically alternative regarding the ambiguous explanation that Smith, Ricardo, and S. Mill made of “civilized society” or “commercial society” to give an account of the scope of a theory value—labor. Beyond the classics, and unlike marginalism, in Marx only abstract labor creates value, the rest of categories, up to reaching the capital concept, have value but do no create value, in like manner, neither technology nor market or circulation create value. This entails a problem for capital, since if production time is a time when value is produced, circulation time is de—valorization time (Fischbach, 2012: 88). From here, we might say, the Marxian theory of value seeks to understand a strictly space—time phenomenon: for the capital it is imperative to accelerate the circulation of commodities and abolish the geographic barriers and their empirical difference, that is to say, annihilate space by means of time [Vernichtung des Raums durch die Zeit] (Marx, 1945: 438). Here, absolute space takes conceptual centrality, not only terminological, as it is a relation of distances between production and circulation of commodities in the logic and totality of capital, since circulation only occurs spatially. Annihilating space is accelerating the time of capital circulation, consequently, in an analytical space, it is a transformation of the categorial use of the absolute space because of their relative use.16

The realization of the logic of capital in space, as a geographic and social place, is foundational if it is considered that the expansion of capital by means of navigation, train and communication media —abolishing geographic barriers and unifying space— allows the creation of the global market (Fischbach, 2012: 87) . Space is a way of capital realization, it is a crystalized social relationship that is carried out in the economic activity of capital, for as capital cannot annihilate space, it needs to produce space, re—spatializing, i.e., by means of a process of territorial expansion and unification, which is the same as the process of creation of the global market. This is what conceptually we may think of as abstract space, namely: the modern action of the capital of spatialize things and all that is founded in it: capital essentially tends to make the world and daily life a space for the valorization of value; and of modernity, a countenance (uneven and combined) of the commodity—producing system.

In the end of the third section, we stated that abstract social domination is the modern form of subornation to impersonal and quasi—independent structures, namely: value and capital incorporated in social work defined by the commodity—producing system, hence the need, as we have noticed, of an immanent critique [Immanente Kritk].

The social domination of capital is carried out and completed in a spatial—temporary manner, as the time of socially necessary labor is a quasi—objective social necessity (Postone, 1993) as spending time on abstract labor, which has absolute space as a way for development and relative and relational space as social relationship crystalized in the spatialization of the things as commodities. This realization of abstract social domination of the capital cannot only be the unfolded social form of the capital logic. It requires a space—time realization, which at general level implicates the subordination of daily (social and individual) experiences to the modern, abstracn and logical paradigm in which the determinations of capital constitute, determine and transcend their particular moments and that, consequently, only exist through those moments.

A privileged way to understand this realization process, in spite of its variable use in critical thinking, is the category of real abstraction. When Sohn—Rethel (2017) states that the “abstraction of commodities” is not a product of thoughts, but actions, not only does he contest Adam Smith for intending to attribute consciousness to the acts of change, but also allows rethinking the problem of value as a particular conceptualization or as a real abstraction (Sohn—Rethel, 2017: 28). The conceptualization of value exists analytically in the mind; however, its origin is strictly social, that is to say, it is in the space—time registration of social relationships, whose mode of social objectivity and subjectivity are real abstractions that come from a space—time activity produced by the capital and extended as effective reality in modernity.

When Lefebvre formulates the theses on the production of space, not only is he interested in understanding the processes of spatial production and reproduction of modern social relationships, but also in the conceptualization of abstraction to think space and production, and their possible categorial extensions to criticize modern urbanism.17 However, as in Lefebvre the reproduction of social relationships of production go beyond the world of labor and production, he carried out an epistemological endeavor to think the space logically as the privileged place from which to locate production and reproduction. For Neil Smith (2020) —and Castells at the beginning—, this stance of Lefebvre entails a substantive political problem: where to locate the focus of political discussion and class struggle? In the field of reproduction of social relationships or in the world of labor? (Smith, 2020). The questions Smith makes lucidly might as well be answered, on one side, with the reading of capital as a totality, while on the other, with a reading of the political as a dimension in the sphere from production to interchange, but also unavoidably in the wide range of life in late capitalism. About this, we may surmise —following Fani Carlos (2019) — that production of space is immanent to social production (as socialization) and as such, it is neither realized nor can it be carried out as an activity alien to the logic of capital. Instead, on the contrary, following an immanent criticism, the reproduction of capital —at least as of the end of the XX century— is carried out by means of the production of space (Carlos, 2019); an issue that remits to the problem of urban space as a space for the reproduction of the capital, and from Lefebvre onwards, to urbanization as social production of space and daily life.

The social reproduction of space

The organization of geography spaces in urban and rural zones has traditionally been associated in the academic, censual, and administrative spheres, with the technical division of agricultural and industrial work. In point of fact, in Marx and Engels (1969) , the division between countryside and city —for the moment, we would say equivalent to rural and urban— is the first spatial manifestation of the technical division of labor, even prior to the formation of large agglomerations associated with industrialization processes. However, after the development of state housing and urbanization policies in the XX century, the urban begins to enter into the political economy from the need of producing the space for the reproduction of capital —mediated by the state— for its part, produced by commodity circulation and the reproduction of labor force (Castells, 1974; Lokjine, 1979; Topalov, 1979) .

While the Marxist debate in Europe and Latin America mainly focused on the reproduction of capital by means of urbanization processes, in parallel Henri Lefebvre started to develop a theory in which the urban is not limited to the spatial organization of the market and labor force, but unfolds as a concept that provides the process of capitalist production with meaning. Lefebvre (2018a) points out that “the dual process of industrialization and urbanization loses all meaning if urban society is not conceived as goal and purpose of industrialization”. It is necessary to clarify that even if industrialization is not synonym to capitalism, it is one of the main vehicles for its development; and in this sense, it is important to pinpoint that Lefebvre does not state urbanization is the essence of capital, but of industrialization. This allows stating the following thesis: the capital, being a social relationship based on the valorization of values, in exploitation and accumulation, not only produces industrialized means of production, to accomplish its enhanced reproduction, but also produces a space, and that same space is an urban space. This last meaning reappears in the Hegelian aura of Lefebvre.

Industrialization was the rule, at least of the hegemony of the English systemic cycle of accumulation and possibly of the American as well, but it might have been otherwise, as shown by Ellen Meiksins Wood (2016) . Well now, as it was not otherwise, as of the XIX century, industrialization appears as a general and differenced norm of accumulation; therefore, the same may be said about industrialization regarding urbanization. Owing to this, it must be stated to what extent the production of space by the capital is necessarily urban. Considering that we already dealt with the concept of space, it is necessary to observe the way Lefebvre conceptualizes it as urban, discussing with it the thesis of the reproduction of labor force that was the particular contribution of Marxism with the urban studies back then.

To deepen his argument, Lefebvre refers to the problem of suburbanization. If urban rationality consisted in reducing circulation times and infrastructure unit costs, necessary to optimize the reproduction of labor force, then, how is it explained that American society started mass processes of demographic dispersion, increasing the costs of urbanization measured by infrastructure and transport? Lefebvre (2015) articulates his urban theory with a broader social theory on the creation of that he calls the Bureaucratic Society of Controlled Consumption. From this idea, not only does he criticize modern urbanism in political key, but also makes it ideologic: there is no urban rationality in strict sense, but a planning of the space to direct it toward consumption. Beyond his capability to notice a qualitative change in his object of analysis, therefore, the need to produce a new social theory in the context of historic change, it is important to point at the impossibility of conciliating a Marxist interpretation supported on the theory of value with an affirmation of this nature. There is need to approach minimally this issue to be able to incorporate Lefebvre’s statements into a critical theory of value.

From the standpoint of the analysis of the capitalist mode of production that Marx makes in Capital, consumption is not part of the reproduction of capital, but the reduction of material conditions of existence, culturally and historically determined. The capital provides value and realizes it in the interchange, not consumption, even if such consumption increases, a situation possible due to various extra—economic factors that require a different sort or research that exceed this word. Wage, social benefits, urban infrastructure, et cetera, are the indistinct conditions of labor reproduction in specific historical—social contexts, as already stated in the sections on the abstract domination of capital. Proposing that urban consumption manages to give an account of the meaning that articulates production of space is not consistent with the specifically capitalist nature of it, and the same is valid for market. Consequently, consumption and market do not define the urban, it is interchange and the demands of circulation what realizes production and within this the reproduction of labor force. Therefore, to incorporate Lefebvre’s contribution into the theory of value, it is necessary to understand consumption as a generalized increment in mercantile production associated to historic—cultural changes in the reproduction of labor. The specifically urban forms of these changes are summarized in the category of consumption fund, developed by Harvey (1990) from Marx. Well now, if the consumption fund spatially represented in suburbs is a form of labor reproduction, then it is not possible to speak in this case of the production of space as specifically capitalist. If the consumption fund is supported on a number of forms of revenue (gain, rent and interest), its existence realizes capitalist production, but does not produce it. Despite the valuable contribution of a critical theory on the real estate sector, Harvey (1990) unnecessarily limits the argument of space production to the secondary circuit of accumulation, which sets the bases for Marx’s most disseminated interpretations on the current real estate boom. There is only production of space, in the specifically capitalist meaning, to the extent that it is produced in a space for the accumulation of capital, where the realization of commodities, for example, real estate, is only a moment.18 Considering such limitations in the category of (urban) consumption fund, what is important in this is there is spatiality in the constitution of the historic—cultural conditions on which reproduction is fixed.

In this way, the following may be stated: wage must reproduce labor in a determined place in the market, though not necessary by the market. As in the case of money, which Marx systematized in the Theories of capital gain, industry, trade, market, etc. are not a priori capitalist experiences of modernity or reality in general (Mann, 2012: 112—116) . Even if one wanted to insist on the problem of the market, it would be necessary to clarify that the problem is the capitalist market or, even, the impossibility of exteriority of immanence of the capitalist market in modernity as Kurz states.19

From this standpoint the suburban experience is then a new space for reproduction, fixed by new historical—cultural conditions marked by wage reassertions, social policy, postwar, American and European hegemony, among others. The point here is to understand that production of space cannot be the results of none of them in particular. Only is it possible a concept of production of space specifically capitalist if it manages to valorize value, increase the magnitude of the capital. Households, as many as they may be, are sold and realized at the interchange, regardless if they are for workers or not. Affirming they are production of space would be to underestimate their importance in commodity realization, even at a widened scale as proposed by Harvey (1978 and 2012b).

Well now, it may be stated that the formation of fixed capital of a country (total fixed investment on machinery and equipment) is the production of space. By the way, the infrastructure that supports the long logistic chains, but also the structuring vitality inside the large population agglomerations, are part of the production of space of the capital. However, the urban problems Lefebvre invites to is not well defined from the concept of the recently stated space production. Lefebvre’s space production emerges together with his urban theory, at once, it surpasses it. When hew presents the real estate booms as a form of space production, and later Harvey (1978) builds his theory on capitalist urbanization from such booms, they do not clarify that these are only the production of a space for the realization of capital, that is, the production of a space of production.

Such reclusiveness is not as problematic if it is though that the production of space has been historically the conquest of America, colonialization projects, deforestation, the extension of the telegraph, the Internet, or the recent macroinfrastructure projects to extract natural resources, as Arboleda (2016) states. To an increasing extent, such production of space has been capitalist, and so is today. The complex in Lefebvre is that such production of space of production is at once, indissolubly capitalist and urban. Let us go back to the beginning of this section; if Lefebvre says that “urbanization becomes the meaning of industrialization”, what is industrialization? Frequently mistaken by manufacture, machinism, robotization, etc. industrialization is nothing but the production of means of production. It is not a formal exercise, though clearly the replacement between the midterm and space before production expresses the core of the problem.

Even in this manner, it is not possible to understand how the production of space is a historic development of the urban. What is quite clear is that for Lefebvre the production of the space melts into a disperse fabric that makes it indistinguishable the urban from the nonurban. Even if the explosion—implosion nuclear metaphors used by Lefebvre and retaken by Brenner (2013) does not seem to explain anything about the urban or nonurban character of space production, they disclose the geographically expansive characters of what presently may be summarized in the thesis of planetary urbanization (Brenner, 2013); at once they allow interpreting urbanization as a decentered process, where the urban does not constitute the gravitational center of rural migrations and the rural—urban division disappears to the extent that global geographic space stops constituting from regions and moves to be composed as an expansive space of global productive and extractive circuits (Arboleda, 2016; Katsikis, 2018) .

Precisely because of this, Brenner (2013) alludes to Amazonia, Siberia and other extreme regions to illustrate planetary urbanization, calling the human settlements in this exploitation regions (frequently extractive enclaves) operational landscapes characterized by a set of forma attributes unthought for the urban: disperse, reduced in size, little dense, etc. When Brenner (2013) and later Katsikis (2018) build the category of operational landscapes and impute it the urban character, they are making the theoretical exercise of thinking the urban in its relation with the production of the space of production. However, in the explanation they frequently allude that such spaces are urban because they are part of the urban process, without ever indicating what the specifically capitalist character of such processes consists in.

With a view to contributing to the theoretical construction started by Lefebvre and updated by Brenner, we may affirm that operational landscapes are urban because they implicate production of space reproduction subsumed in the production of space production. Being the concept of operation landscape categorically useful, the issue not resolved in Brenner’s (2013) theory of planetary urbanization is that it assumes the inherence of an “urban process” as though the goal of society were urbanization. This is not compatible with a critique of the political economy of space, due to what we previously pointed out: urbanization is subsumed in the production space. Indeed, in Lefebvre there is a concept of urban process, though not autonomous, considering that, as we have stated, urbanization is the sense of industrialization, not of capitalist production.

Brenner’s (2013) contribution to the development of Lefebvre’s statements allows deepening into some questions that might connect the planetary urbanization thesis with the capitalist production of space. In the first place, if scattered human settlements abound in the operation landscapes, why do not call such settlements rural? Is not in any case the rural space subsumed in the capitalist production of space? Here a substantial matter is at stake? The belief that the rural expresses exteriority to the capital is equivocal and seems to be among Brenner’s (2013) suppositions. Did rural China need urbanization to complete its capitalist integration in the form of market socialism? Is not it supposed that, according to the largest part of Marxists historiography, capitalism has an agrarian origin? Should we not moderate the importance of the city in the dawn of capital?

The rural and the agricultural are different dimensions, but if the difference between industry and agriculture is based on that this does not produce its main production means, something similar takes places wit the rural: there is no production of the space of reproduction. If agricultural work is nor peasant, but fundamentally salaried,20 does the market manage to expand salary goods and services to the rural space? Or should rural population travel to an urban space to realize their wage? The same occurs with the set of reproduction infrastructures that are the material base for urbanization. Albeit, this does not prevent the global market from being reproduced and consumed in an increasingly articulated manner in the rural space.

The relevant issue is that if we were able to define the rural, we might say that it is characterized by a sub—provision of urban infrastructure and equipment, at once, rurality is experienced in practice not daily but periodically, in strict sense, monthly, traveling to the center of the reference town to realize the salary, a specifically urban interchange practice, which if becomes stronger turns into rural—urban migration of agricultural laborers even without public reconversion, since agricultural workers may be urban. In this sense, without a specific theory that integrates the production of the space of reproduction in the capitalist production, the Lefebvre’s argument does not allow positioning the urban in the immanent critique to modern society.

Conclusion

From the critique of political economy, late Marx’s project, we have set to dialogue with some of the basic theories on the production of modern space. We coined the term critique to the political economy of space, whose conceptual use, as we have seen, entails an immanent criticism to modernity. This critique is to the abstract logic of value and its expression in the social production of abstract space—time. We have stated that abstract space—time and its indivisible unit are one single great moment of modern social production, whose concrete realization, the urban space, is the geographic space produced for the reproduction of capital, the interchange place, where the totality of mercantile production is realized, while urbanization is presented as the production of interdependent human settlements, socialized by capital, though their meaning is industrialization, not capitalist production. We consider that it is necessary to understand the subsuming of the rural but at once, the limits of such subsuming, since the categorial pair urban—rural refers reproduction not production. Owing to that, it may be said that Marx and Engels (1974) —in spite of having conception of the urban/rural remitted to the technical division of labor— managed to grasp that a dissolution of the urban and the rural is not possible without surpassing abstract human labor, a requirement for building the common, or at least to think post—capitalism: “the abolition of the antithesis between city and countryside is one of the first conditions for community” (1974: 55—56). If we assume that every modern production of space is urban, we may think that the challenge is not to dissolve the urban and the rural, a task elicited, though not concluded in urbanization, but to overcome the urban and the socialized humanity by the abstract logic of valorization that produces, subsumes and dominates modern space—time.

Referencias

Adorno, Theodor (1975), Die Vorlesungen, Alemania: Suhrkamp Verlag. [ Links ]

Akerlof, George y Shiller, Robert (2016), La economía de la manipulación. Cómo caemos como incautos en las trampas del mercado, España: Planeta. [ Links ]

Arboleda, Martín (2016), “Spaces of Extraction, Metropolitan Explosions: Planetary Urbanization and the Commodity in Latin America”, en International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, vol. 40, núm. 1, Inglaterra: Wiley-Blackwell. [ Links ]

Backhaus, Hans-Georg (1997), Dialektik der Wertform Untersuchungen zur marxschen Ökonomiekritik, Alemania: Ça ira Verlag. [ Links ]

Bellamy Foster, John (2008), La ecología de Marx. Materialismo y naturaleza, España: Viejo Topo. [ Links ]

Bellofiore, Riccardo (2018a), Le avventure della socializzazione: Dalla teoria monetaria del valore alla teoria macro-monetaria della produzione capitalistica, Italia: Mimesis Edizioni. [ Links ]

Bellofiore, Riccardo (2018b), “C’è vita su Marx? Il Capitale nel bicentenario”, en Consecutio Rerum, vol. 3, núm. 5, Italia: Edizione Efesto. [ Links ]

Bielschowsky, Ricardo (2010), Sesenta años de la CEPAL: textos seleccionados del decenio 1998-2008, Argentina: Comisión Económica para América Latina y el Caribe y Siglo XXI. [ Links ]

Brenner, Neil (2013), “Tesis sobre la urbanización planetaria”, en Nueva Sociedad, núm. 243, Argentina: Friedrich Ebert Stiftung. [ Links ]

Carlos, Ana Fani (2007). O espaço urbano. Novos escritos sobre a cidade, São Paulo: Faculdade de filosofia, letras e ciências humanas universidade de são paulo (fflch). [ Links ]

Carlos, Ana Fani (2019), “Geografia no século XX: o caminho da crítica e a dialética da produção social do espaço”, en Conceição, Alexandrina y Silva, Jose [eds.], O fim do pensamento crítico reflexivo? A negação do humano e a banalização da teoría, Brasil: Universidad Federal de Sergipe. [ Links ]

Elden, Stuart (2004), Understanding Henri Lefebvre: Theory and the Possible, Inglaterra: Continuum. [ Links ]

Castells, Manuel (1974),La cuestión urbana, México: Siglo XXI. [ Links ]

Dussel, Enrique (1985), La producción teórica de Marx. Un comentario a los Grundrisse, México: Siglo XXI . [ Links ]

Dussel, Enrique (1984), Filosofía de la producción, Bolivia: Nueva América. [ Links ]

Fischbach, Franck [ed.] (2012), Marx. Releer El Capital, España: Akal. [ Links ]

Gottdiener, Mark (1985), The Social Production of Urban Space, Estados Unidos: University of Texas Press. [ Links ]

Harvey, David (1978), “The urban process under capitalism: a framework for analysis”, en International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, vol. 2, núm. 3, Inglaterra: Wiley-Blackwell . [ Links ]

Harvey, David (1990), Los límites del capitalismo y la teoría marxista, México: Fondo de Cultura Económica. [ Links ]

Harvey, David (2007), Urbanismo y desigualdad social, España: Siglo XXI. [ Links ]

Harvey, David (2012a), “La Geografía como oportunidad política de resistencia y construcción de alternativas”, en Espacios. Revista de Geografía, vol. 2, núm. 4, Chile: Universidad Academia de Humanismo Cristiano. [ Links ]

Harvey, David (2012b), Ciudades Rebeldes. Del derecho de la ciudad a la revolución urbana, España: Akal . [ Links ]

Harvey, David (2018), Justicia, naturaleza y geografía de la diferencia, España: Traficantes de sueños. [ Links ]

Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (2010), Fenomenología del espíritu, México: Fondo de Cultura Económica . [ Links ]

Heidegger, Martin (2009), El arte y el espacio, España: Herder. [ Links ]

Heinrich, Michael (2018), Crítica de la economía política. Una Introducción a El Capital de Marx, España: Escolar y Mayo. [ Links ]

Horkheimer, Max (1996), Gesammelte Schriften in 19 Bänden, Alemania: Fischer Verlag. [ Links ]

Katsikis, Nikos (2018), “The ‘Other’ Horizontal Metropolis: Landscapes of Urban Interdependence”, en Vigano, Paola et al. [eds.], The Horizontal Metropolis Between Urbanism and Urbanization, Estados Unidos: Springer International Publishing. [ Links ]

Krugman, Paul (1999), Economía espacial: las ciudades, las regiones y el comercio internacional, España: Ariel. [ Links ]

Kurz, Robert (1994), “Der Ende der Politik, Thesen zur Krise des warenförmigen Regulationssystems”, en Krisis. Beiträge zur Kritik der Warengesellschaft, vol. 14, Alemania: Horlemann Verlag. [ Links ]

Kurz, Robert (2016), El colapso de la modernización. Del derrumbe del socialismo de cuartel a la crisis de la economía mundial, Argentina: Marat. [ Links ]

Kurz, Robert (2021), La sustancia del capital, España: Enclave de libros. [ Links ]

Lefebvre, Henry (1980), Hegel, Marx, Nietzsche, España: Siglo XXI . [ Links ]

Lefebvre, Henry (2013), La producción del espacio, España: Capitán Swing. [ Links ]

Lefebvre, Henry (2015), La revolución urbana, Chile: Praxis. [ Links ]

Lefebvre, Henry (2018a), El derecho a la ciudad, Chile: Praxis . [ Links ]

Lefebvre, Henry (2018b), Espacio y política, Chile: Praxis . [ Links ]

Lefebvre, Henry (2018c), De lo rural a lo urbano, Chile: Praxis . [ Links ]

Lokjine, Jean (1979),El marxismo, el Estado y la cuestión urbana, España: Siglo XXI . [ Links ]

Mann, Geoff (2012), “State of Confusion: Money and the Space of Civil Society in Hegel and Gramsci”, en Ekers, Michael et al. [eds.],Gramscian Geographies, Inglaterra: Wiley Blackwell. [ Links ]

Marx, Karl y Engels, Friedrich (1969), Die deutsche Ideologie. Kritik der neuesten deutschen Philosophie in ihren Repräsentanten Feuerbach, B. Bauer und Stirner, und des deutschen Sozialismus in seinen verschiedenen Propheten, Werke, Band 3, S. 5 - 530, Alemania: Dietz Verlag. [ Links ]

Marx, Karl (1945), Grundrisse der Kritik der politischen Ökonomie, Alemania: Europäische Verlagsanstalt. [ Links ]

Marx, Karl (1978), Briefe, en Karl Marx-Friedrich Engels Werke [MEW] B. 29, Berlín, Dietz. [ Links ]

Marx, Karl (2012), Das Kapital. Kritik der politischen Ökonomie, III . Marx, K. & Engels, F., Werke, tomo 25, Alemania: Dietz Verlag . [ Links ]

Marx, Karl y Engels, Friedrich (2009), El Capital. Crítica de la economía política. Libro III El proceso global de la producción capitalista, vol. 8, México: Siglo XXI . [ Links ]

Marx, Karl y Engels, Friedrich (1974), La ideología alemana. Crítica de la novísima filosofía alemana en las personas de sus representantes L.Feuerbach, B. Bauer y Stirner y del socialismo alemán en las de sus diferentes profetas, España: Grijalbo. [ Links ]

Meiksins Wood, Ellen (2016), “Los orígenes agrarios del capitalismo”, enMonthly Review, núm. 2, Estados Unidos: Monthly Review Press. [ Links ]

Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1966), Sens et non-sens, Francia: Gallimard. [ Links ]

Moore, Jason (2020), El capitalismo en la trama de la vida. Ecología y acumulación de capital, España: Traficantes de sueños . [ Links ]

Postone, Moishe (1993), Time, Labor, and Social Domination. A Reinterpretation of Marx's Critical Theory, Reino Unido: Cambridge University Press. [ Links ]

Reichelt, Helmut (2001), Zur logischen Struktur des Kapitalbegriffs bei Karl Marx, Alemania: Europäische Verlagsanstalt . [ Links ]

Roberts, Michael (2018), “La ley del valor de Marx: un debate entre David Harvey y Michael Roberts”. Disponible en: https://cubayeconomia.blogspot.com [16 de septiembre de 2021]. [ Links ]

Schmid, Christian (2005), Stadt, Raum und Gesellschaft: Henri Lefebvre und die Theorie der Produktion des Raumes, Alemania: Steiner. [ Links ]

Shields, Rob (1999), Lefebvre, Love and Struggle: Spatial Dialectics, Inglaterra: Routledge. [ Links ]

Smith, Neil (2020), Desarrollo desigual. Naturaleza, capital y la producción del espacio, España: Traficantes de sueños . [ Links ]

Sohn-Rethel, Alfred (2017), Trabajo manual y trabajo intelectual. Una crítica de la epistemología, España: Dado Ediciones. [ Links ]

Stiglitz, Joseph (2006), Cómo hacer que funcione la globalización, España: Taurus. [ Links ]

Stanek, Lukasz (2008) Space As Concrete Abstraction: Hegel, Marx, And Modern Urbanism In Henri Lefebvre. En Goonewardena, B. et al, Space, Difference, Everyday Life. Reading Henri Lefebvre, New York: Routledge [ Links ]

Topalov, Christian (1979),La urbanización capitalista, México: Edicol. [ Links ]

Received: December 01, 2021; Accepted: May 06, 2022

Creative Commons License Este es un artículo publicado en acceso abierto bajo una licencia Creative Commons